âarithmogeometric unitsââe.g., an extended line drawn from two points, plane figures such as triangles and rectangles from several lines, a circle from a joined curved line, and three-dimensional spatial objects such as pyramids cubes, spheres, and complex polyhedra from plane figures. As Aristotle states, based on these inquires âthe Pythagoreans . . . construct the whole universe out of numbersâonly not numbers consisting of abstract units: they suppose the units to have spatial magnitude.â 4
Thus the Pythagoreans were able to represent the four elements of the physical worldâearth, air, fire, and waterâby four polyhedra: the earth by the 4-sided pyramid or tetrahedron, air by the 6-sided cube, fire by the 8-sided octahedron, water by the 20-sided icosahedron, and the universe itself by the 12-sided dodecahedron. Because Plato apparently assigned different polyhedra to the four elements, explaining their disintegration and reconfiguration as due to the separation and recombination of their constituent plane figures, they came to be known as âthe five Platonic solids.â Kepler in the early seventeenth century began his astronomical theorizing in his Mysterium Cosmographicum (The Cosmographic Mystery) with the five polyhedra of Pythagoras perhaps as revised by Plato. Other of their astronomical contributions also were extremely important, such as Eudoxus of Cnidus who made the determination of the solar year to be 365 days and five hours, along with originating the long-prevailing view that the celestial bodies revolve on a series of concentric spheres with the earth in the center.
His pupil Callippus of Cyzicus increased his number of spheres to thirty-four to account for certain astronomical irregularities that were adopted by Aristotle. But Philolaus of Croton, in 259 BCE, astutely assigned âan oblique circular motionâ to the earth around a central fire while Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantos of Syracuse attributed to it an axial rotation from west to east to explain the apparent rising and setting of the sun, along with determining that Mercury and Venus revolve around the sun. This culminated in Aristarchus of Samosâs prescient sun-centered astronomical theory in the third century BCE, though eclipsed by Ptolemyâs geocentrism until Copernicusâs adoption of heliocentrism.
These celestial innovations were complemented by such empirical theories as Empedoclesâ conception of the four elements, earth, air, fire, and water, as basic; Anaxagorasâ rejection of Empedoclesâ four elements as too limited, declaring that the original mixture consisted of an infinite number of infinitely divisible particles that were representative of all the diversity of things, but too minute to be discernable except for air and aither; Leucippusâ and Democritusâ astute atomic theory that the underlying matter of the universe consisted of solid, indivisible, insensible particles that varied in their size, shapes, solidity, and motions, excluding sensory qualities. 5
However, deriding such empirical explanations Plato, in his famous âallegory of the cave,â described sensory knowledge as mere reflections of the imperfect material objects in the physical world or âReceptacle,â declaring that mathematics could free one from these perceptual illusions to ascend to the intelligible world of perfect archetypes, the âRealm of Forms,â culminating in the âForm of the Goodâ and the âDemiurge.â Apparently the latter was the creator of the real world by imposing the ideal archetypes on the imperfect Receptacle. 6 It was Platoâs philosophy that was the most influential during the medieval period because of its easy conformity with Christianity, interpreting his Demiurge as God.
Yet it was not Platoâs philosophy but that of his pupil Aristotle that would prove the most dominant from the thirteenth to