a very technical monograph, I was
able only to hint at some of the problems that characterize life in the
Western industrial nations, problems that I find profoundly disturbing.1
I began that study in the belief that the roots of our dilemma were
social and economic in nature; by the time I had completed it, I was
convinced that I had omitted a whole epistemological dimension. I began
to feel, in other words, that something was wrong with our entire world
view. Western life seems to be drifting toward increasing entropy,
economic and technological chaos, ecological disaster, and ultimately,
psychic dismemberment and disintegration; and I have come to doubt that
sociology and economics can by themselves generate an adequate explanation
for such a state of affairs.
The present book, then, is an attempt to take my previous analysis one
step further; to grasp the modern era, from the sixteenth century to
the present, as a whole, and to come to terms with the metaphysical
presuppositions that define this period. This is not to treat mind,
or consciousness, as an independent entity, cut off from material
life; I hardly believe such is the case. For purposes of discussion,
however, it is often necessary to separate these two aspects of human
experience; and although I shall make every effort to demonstrate their
interpenetration, my primary focus in this book is the transformations
of the human mind. This emphasis stems from my conviction that the
fundamental issues confronted by any civilization in its history, or by
any person in his or her life, are issues of meaning . And historically,
our loss of meaning in an ultimate philosophical or religious sense --
the split between fact and value which characterizes the modern age --
is rooted in the Scientific Revolution of the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries. Why should this be so?
The view of nature which predominated in the West down to the eve of
the Scientific Revolution was that of an enchanted world. Rocks, trees,
rivers, and clouds were all seen as wondrous, alive, and human beings
felt at home in this environment. The cosmos, in short, was a place
of belonging . A. member of this cosmos was not an alienated observer
of it but a direct participant in its drama. His personal destiny was
bound up with its destiny, and this relationship gave meaning to his
life. This type of consciousness -- what I shall refer to in this book
as "participating consciousness" -- involves merger, or identification,
with one's surroundings, and bespeaks a psychic wholeness that has long
since passed from the scene. Alchemy, as it turns out, was the last
great coherent expression of participating consciousness in the West.
The story of the modern epoch, at least on the level of mind, is
one of progressive disenchantment. From the sixteenth century on,
mind has been progressively expunged from the phenomenal world. At
least in theory, the reference points for all scientific explanation
are matter and motion -- what historians of science refer to as the
"mechanical philosophy." Developments that have thrown this world view
into question -- quantum mechanics, for example, or certain types of
contemporary ecological research -- have not made any significant dent
in the dominant mode of thinking. That mode can best be described as
disenchantment, nonparticipation, for it insists on a rigid distinction
between observer and observed. Scientific consciousness is alienated
consciousness: there is no ecstatic merger with nature, but rather total
separation from it. Subject and object are always seen in opposition
to each other. I am not my experiences, and thus not really a part
of the world around me. The logical end point of this world view is a
feeling of total reification: everything is an object, alien, not-me;
and I am ultimately an object too, an alienated "thing" in a world of
other, equally meaningless things. This world is not of my own